On Petitionary Prayer, Part I, Ljiljana Radenovic

And he went a little farther, and fell on his face, and prayed, saying, O my Father, if it be possible, let this cup pass from me: nevertheless not as I will, but as thou wilt.—Matthew 26:39.

In Aldous Huxley’s biography of Father Joseph (Grey Eminence 1941), a monk but also Cardinal de Richelieu’s minister of foreign affairs, we find Father Joseph during the siege of La Rochelle praying (and asking Calvarian nuns to pray) for a number of curious things: “for the success of Father Joseph’s pet plan for entering the town by night through an underground sewer and taking the garrison by surprise”, “for the conversion of the Protestant Duke of La Tremoille”, “for an amelioration in the behaviour of the King’s brother Gaston”, “for the defeat of the second English expedition”, and so on. By describing Father Joseph’s political engagement, Huxley masterfully highlights a tension between his ‘political’ prayers and the life of pure contemplation in which Father Joseph’s own will is supposed to be annihilated and joined with God’s. … [please read below the rest of the article].

Giovanni Bellini, “Agony in the Garden” (c. 1459–1465)

Article Citation:

Radenovic, Ljiljana. 2024. “On Petitionary Prayer.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 13 (4): 41–52. https://wp.me/p1Bfg0-8JM.

🔹 The PDF of the article gives the complete text and specific page numbers.

Editor’s Note: Ljiljana Radenovic’s article “On Petitionary Prayer”, will be presented in two parts. Please find below Part I. Please refer to Part II.

Highlighted Resources:

❦ Radenovic, Ljiljana. 2023. “Alternative Modernity and Its Discontents.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 12 (1): 32-38.

❦ Radenovic, Ljiljana. 2023. “How Christianity Became Platonism for the Masses.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 12 (7): 1-6.

Father Joseph’s political prayers may strike us as misguided and misplaced, compared to petitionary prayers for the health and well-being of loved ones. Still such prayers are common among the faithful. Indeed, praying alone does not guarantee the prayer will be met. Priests in their sermons have always advised their fellow Christians to follow Jesus’ example and pray just like Jesus prayed for ‘the cup to pass him’, not according to his will but according to the will of the Father. In other words, we can pray to God for healing or prosperity or some other matter, but we should accept any outcome with gratitude, as it is God’s will.

In addition to this common misunderstanding of how petitionary prayer ‘works’, the way we make sense of it and its place in our faith has become particularly problematic in the last several centuries. That is, the understanding of what constitutes proper scientific explanation (and proper causal powers operating in nature) has changed to exclude the possibility of the intervention of supernatural force. This fairly recent scientific worldview disqualifies petitionary prayer altogether because, according to it, such prayer presupposes a faulty causal link between supernatural and natural phenomena; namely, it aims to accomplish an outcome in this world through supernatural means. As Wittgenstein argues, if we use prayer to make something happen here and now, we are treating prayer as pseudo-science (Wittgenstein 2020) and are engaging in superstitious not religious activity.

In the Concept of Prayer D.Z. Phillips (1965)[1] builds on Wittgenstein’s remarks to develop a broader view of petitionary prayer. Phillips explains that, when done correctly, a proper petitionary prayer is not a prayer for God’s intervention but a believer’s attempt to be at peace with God’s will. In this way, Phillips keeps the realms of science and faith separate and accommodates petitionary prayer to a modern worldview that does not permit supernatural causation. But is it really accurate to say that a believer does not pray for a specific outcome—the recovery of a child, life of a terminally ill friend, pregnancy—when no medical help seems to work? And when the believer does pray for these things, is she really committing the sin of superstition? None of this sounds right. To find an answer, in what follows, I explore Wittgenstein’s and Phillips’ understanding of petitionary prayer and ask where their views of science, faith, and superstition come from.

Wittgenstein and D.Z. Phillips: Petitionary Prayer and Superstition

Wittgenstein made only a few comments about the distinction between proper faith and superstition, but as always with Wittgenstein, these comments are telling. In one instance, he says: “Religious faith and superstition are entirely different. One of them springs from fear and is a kind of false science. The other is a trusting” (Wittgenstein, cited in Malcolm 1993, 18). What Wittgenstein is saying is that while true faith is nourished by our love of God, whereby we put our trust in God’s will and accept the plan God has for us, our superstitious acts are the result of a lack of this trust. Through superstitious acts, we try to convince God to intervene and do what we think is best for us. When we engage in such acts, we try to influence future events and achieve a desired end: to get a job, to recover from illness, to travel safely, to win a war. In this way, we implicitly presuppose a causal link between our acts, God, and the happenings in the world. For Wittgenstein, this kind of superstition is a pseudo-science, a pseudo-technological stance through which we are attempting to regain control of the world.

It is important to note that for Wittgenstein, superstition is not confined to avoiding black cats, casting spells, and making voodoo dolls. It can also appear in formal religious practices, such as baptism. Baptizing a child so the child will be healthy and prosperous is superstitious. Baptizing a child to initiate the child in faith and make her a member of the Christian church is a sign of proper faith.

While Wittgenstein’s clear-cut distinction between faith and superstition is easy to draw in some cases, the case of petitionary prayer presents a difficulty. People pray for various reasons: to converse with God, to connect, to share their love, to repent, to surrender themselves to God, but they also pray to ask God to help them with their immediate worries. These various functions of prayer cannot be easily disentangled. As his comments to his friends and his personal diaries show, Wittgenstein himself prayed. During WWI, we find him praying to be brave: “How will I behave when it comes to shooting? I am not afraid of being shot but of not doing my duty properly. God give me strength! Amen!”(Wittgenstein, cited in Malcolm 1993, 8-9).

Should this kind of prayer be regarded as superstition? After all, Wittgenstein asks God to give him strength and courage. Isn’t he presupposing a faulty causal link and thus committing a superstitious act in his prayer? We may explain away this tension by saying that what he is really doing is trying to build up his own morale and not fail his fellow soldiers. We could say that there is nothing more to these prayers than self-encouragement, but Wittgenstein does not provide further clarification about what exactly he is doing when praying, neither at the time he was writing these words during the war nor later.

DZ. Phillips attempts to develop the Wittgensteinian view of prayer, and in his Concept of Prayer (1965), he devotes a chapter to petitionary prayer. He acknowledges that every petitionary prayer seems to be intended to make a difference in this world. The prayer asks for a particular “this” or “that”, as Phillips notes, and in this way, it seems to presuppose a causal link between a prayer and a desired outcome. But if this is really the case, petitionary prayer will be a lot like a spell. So if a prayer is to make a difference in the world, what does this mean, and can we distinguish it from an incantation or a cry for help in times of danger? In other words, can there be a proper petitionary prayer that does not end up being superstition or a sign of distress?

To answer these questions, Phillips asks us to take a closer look at the context of prayer and the role it plays in an individual’s life. If the person does not pray regularly but only in extreme, out-of-the-ordinary situations, it is more likely that the prayer is incantation, a spell intended to get a particular thing done; in other words, it’s likely to be a superstition. But even here, we need to be careful and make fine distinctions. If somebody calls on God only when in danger, can this be disregarded as a mere exclamation or request for help, not of God but of a fellow human? In fact, Phillips finds nothing particularly religious in such an act. It might not be even superstition, as it stems from the desire to give our stress a voice. Now, if we consistently pray and negotiate with God in stressful times, this could be closer to what we would consider superstition.

According to Phillips, such negotiations with God stand in contrast to Psalm 23: “Yea I walk through the valley of the shadow of death I will fear no evil for thou art with me”. In the former case, infrequent petition, the prayer presupposes God can intervene and make a difference in the outcome. The latter, frequent petition, acknowledges the dependence between us and God and expresses complete trust in God and God’s will. But Phillips is aware that most prayers come in the form of the former and seem to presuppose the possibility of God’s intervention. Even Wittgenstein’s prayer that he wrote on the Eastern front during the war asks God to give him faith, strength, and courage to endure and be brave in the face of death.

Phillips further argues, along with the Church and Desert Fathers, that if a believer thinks praying hard will make a difference and asks “Didn’t I pray hard enough?” when praying “fails”, this means the prayer is closer to superstition than to a religious act. So before we decide if a prayer is a superstition or an act of faith, we need to know the context: when, how, and by whom it is uttered, its motivation, and its spirit. What surely does not matter in prayer is the actual words and their order: “Prayers, unlike certain spells, are not ruined by a slip of a tongue” (Phillips 1965, 119).

Still, the question remains: What does it mean for a believer to ask God for the quick recovery of a sick child? Phillips argues there is no causal relationship between the prayer and the recovery of the child (should the child recover). It is not the case that praying caused God to save the child, and the child’s recovery is not evidence that the prayer worked. What believers do in petitionary prayer is to acknowledge “their own helplessness, that the way things go is beyond their control and seek something to sustain them which does not depend on the way things go, namely, the love of God” (Phillips 1965, 120). “It is true,” Phillips says, “that God’s will can be found in whatever happens, but the prayer of petition is best understood, not as an attempt at influencing the way things go, but as an expression of, and a request for, devotion to God through the way things go” (Phillips 1965, 120). Then, if the child gets better, it is an occasion to express gratitude for all God’s blessings, including this one. If this is what the prayer is about, it is an act of faith. Anything else, and it is superstition.

Why, then, do believers mention specific hopes and desires? Why don’t they just pray for God’s will? In fact, Phillips says bringing up specific wishes and fears helps the believer reconcile himself with the will of God: “After all it is these desires and not any others which threaten to overwhelm him, and through which he must seek God” (Phillips 1965, 122).

In his concluding remarks, Phillips explains the status of the petitionary prayer that Wittgenstein wrote during the war. He argues that in all prayers in which we ask God to strengthen our faith, to have more love, or to have more hope, we bring God to life in us, so the connection between ourselves and God is not left to be external. In other words, when we pray to God to be brave and do the right thing, we do not ask for external help but for help from within. Applying this insight to Wittgenstein’s case, we may conclude that he did not engage in superstition when he prayed on the frontlines of combat.

But is Phillips’ description of petitionary prayer really what the deeply religious do when they pray? Are they simply asking for God’s grace to strengthen their faith so they can endure whatever comes and nothing else? Phillips has been criticized (Van Herck 2016; Sweetman 2014; but also defended, see Whittaker 2008; Brenner 2009) for not describing what the deeply religious actually do when they pray but rather prescribing what the religious should do in their prayers. More specifically, he has been criticized for imposing on believers a philosophical distinction between proper faith and superstition based on his own outsider’s view. This may indeed be the case. But why does he feel the need to do so? Petitionary prayer has always been endorsed by the Christian clergy[2] and laity (with the aforementioned caveats). Today, if we happen to be on Christian twitter, we may see pleas from fellow Christians to pray for a particular case: quick recovery of a child, successful job application, parents’ health, and many more, sometimes not named, private intentions.

Moreover, when we take a look at the texts and letters of the Desert Fathers, we see petitionary prayer was common among early Christians. Their prayers seem to presuppose the belief in God’s miracles. But the metaphysics of our modern times places a special burden on petitionary prayer because it excludes the possibility of miracles—hence, Phillips’ need to give it a narrower meaning and disregard everything else as superstition.

Metaphysical Confines

As we might expect, the worlds of the Desert Fathers of Late Antiquity and the 20th century Wittgensteinians are profoundly different. The world of the Desert Fathers is an ordered, moral universe governed by both worldly and other-worldly rules (Martin 2004, 200–204). The contemporary world of Wittgenstein and D.Z. Phillips is a dead, material, and mechanical universe of “efficient” causation, indifferent to human sense of good and evil (see Milbank 2022). For the Desert Fathers, transgressing the moral and natural laws[3] of this world by requesting non-Christian powers for help is forbidden magic akin to superstition. This does not mean that superstition will not work. On the contrary, summoning magical powers might bring us the desired outcome here and now but at the cost of the salvation of our soul. Still, praying to God for help is more than welcome.

For Wittgensteinians, superstition is the belief in a (false) causal chain, i.e., the belief in a supernatural intervention that will make a difference in this world. Hence, in proper prayer, we should refrain from requesting such an intervention. If we pray in this way, we are slipping into superstition. In other words, for contemporary Wittgensteinians, any intervention in this world is reserved for a joint venture of science and technology and is made possible by the laws of nature, while God’s miracles are simply flights of imagination.

A historically inaccurate but very popular story about how we arrived at such a worldview goes as follows: [4] since the 17th century (with some earlier precursors), we have been witnessing the process of disenchantment with natural forces. Instead of turning to moral agents and the Aristotelian four causes, we explain worldly events and phenomena via mechanical (efficient) causation. In the last 300 years or so, we have slowly accepted that to explain any change in nature (from billiard balls colliding to the biological processes of growth), we need to look for a particular physical cause and the natural law that covers it. Once we identify both, we have successfully explained the phenomenon.

What does this epistemological move mean for our ontology? Well, it seems that nothing non-extended and immaterial can operate in nature. In other words, nature and everything in it become physical through and through. Non-physical, spiritual forces disappear and cease to be valid contenders for a proper natural explanation. Once we find ourselves in this disenchanted universe, the struggle to make our soul fit into it yields a variety of dualist (Descartes), monist (Spinoza), or materialist (La Mettrie) philosophies.

By the end of the 19th and early 20th century, materialists had prevailed. By then, beyond the state of our soul, God had become a problem. Now, even if we grant there is God and that at the beginning of time, God created the whole of nature in some unknown way, we are not allowed to believe in God’s miracles because it makes no physical (scientific!) sense to have a non-natural, non-physical cause of a natural phenomenon. The new metaphysics excludes an interventionist God, even if it allows a transcendent one.

Another interesting aspect of the disenchantment with nature is the loss of its moral quality. Good and evil cease to operate in this world. Moral forces vanish along with moral purposes (teleological causation). Nature is left bare and indifferent. Life and death become neutral and natural phenomena. There is no moral drama in sickness, no Daimons who can hurt us, no prayers that can heal. The world changes from a highly meaningful one in which human drama unfolds to an indifferent world of simple mechanics.

By the end of the 19th and the start of the 20th century, the materialist, reductive, scientific worldview had won, and philosophers either attempted to reconcile faith and science or else dismissed the whole of faith as superstition. The thinkers who drew a line between faith and science and thus shaped our modern take on superstition were the early analytic philosophers: Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, and logical positivists of the Vienna circle. Through the logical analysis of language, they clarified the distinction between proper areas of empirical study and misguided and nonsensical metaphysical speculations.[5] According to these philosophers, the role of sciences is to deal with the world, explore it, and discover which hypotheses are true and which are false. Only theories that can be empirically verified are scientific. The rest belong to the sphere of nonsense, i.e., metaphysics, and should either be discarded (logical positivists) or saved for inspiration and meaningful life (Wittgenstein).

Once we are confined to the natural world in this narrow sense, questions about good and evil, beautiful and ugly, faith and lack of faith in God, and the like are left outside of legitimate, even meaningful, scientific inquiry. Within this new reductive scientific metaphysics, religious faith is discarded as superstition or partially saved because it has the special role of providing our lives with meaning. Either way, it ceases to be a part of legitimate knowledge of the world and, as such, should never intertwine with the proper realm of science. When it does (through ignorance or by mistake), it turns into superstition.

With those thoughts in mind, let me go back to the metaphysics of pre-modern times and the metaphysics of modernity, this time looking specifically into the different understandings of God’s intervention and miracles. Such an inquiry can shed light on the way our metaphysics shapes our understanding of faith, God, superstition, and proper faith. This kind of history is particularly hard to do because we tend to impose our own understanding of natural, possible, and supernatural on the worldviews of the past, unaware of our own metaphysical limitations.

❧ Please refer to Part II of Ljiljan Radenovic’s “On Petitionary Prayer”.

Acknowledgements

This paper was created as part of the scientific research project “Science, Faith, and Superstition” funded by the Ian Ramsay Centre for Science and Religion, Oxford and Templeton Foundation.

Author Information:

Ljiljana Radenovic, lradenovic72@gmail.com, is Associate Professor at the Department of Philosophy, University of Belgrade. Her main research interests fall into the field of philosophy and history of cognitive science, history of emotions, developmental psychology, and philosophy of biology.

References

Barsanuphius and John. 2007. Letters, Volume 2, translated by John Chryssavgis. Catholic University of America Press.

Brenner, William H. 2009. “D.Z. Phillips and Classical Theism.” New Blackfriars 90 (1025): 17-37.

Brown, Peter. 1981. The Cult of the Saints: Its Rise and Function in Latin Christianity. University of Chicago Press.

Hanby, Michael. 2022. “Questioning the Science and Religion Question.” In After Science and Religion: Fresh Perspectives from Philosophy and Theology, edited by Peter Harrison and John Milbank, 155-170. Cambridge University Press.

Harrison, Peter. 2020. The Territories of Science and Religion. University of Chicago Press.

Harrison, Peter and John Milbank, eds. 2022. After Science and Religion: Fresh Perspectives from Philosophy and Theology. Cambridge University Press.

Hume, David. 1957. The Natural History of Religion. Stanford University Press.

Huxley, Aldous. 1941. Grey Eminence: A Study in Religion and Politics. London: Chatto & Windus.

James, William. 1985. The Varieties of Religious Experience. Edited by Martin E. Marty. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Lavan, Luke A. 2008. “Explaining Technological Change: Innovation, Stagnation, Recession and Replacement.” In Technology in Transition A.D. 300-650 (Late Antique Archaeology 4), edited by Luke Lavan, Enrico Zanini, and Alexander Sarantis, xv-xl. Leiden: Brill.

Malcolm, Norman. 1993. Wittgenstein: A Religious Point of View? Edited and with a response by Peter Winch. London: Routledge.

Martin, Dale B. 2004. Inventing Superstition: From the Hippocratics to the Christians. Harvard University Press.

Milbank, John. 2022. Religion, Science and Magic. After Science and Religion: Fresh Perspectives from Philosophy and Theology, ed. P. Harrison, J. Milbank, p.75-144.

Oyama, Susan. 2000. The Ontogeny of Information: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Duke University Press.

Phillips, D. Z. 2016. “Philosophy, Piety and Petitionary Prayer–A Reply to Walter van Herck.” In D.Z. Phillips’ Contemplative Philosophy of Religion: Questions and Responses, edited by Andy F. Sanders, 139-152. London: Routledge.

Phillips, D. Z. 1965. The Concept of Prayer. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Phillips, D. Z. and Timothy Tessin, eds. 1999. Religion and Hume’s Legacy. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

Radenovic, Ljiljana. 2023a. “Alternative Modernity and Its Discontents.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 12 (1): 32-38.

Radenovic, Ljiljana. 2023b. “How Christianity Became Platonism for the Masses.” Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 12 (7): 1-6.

Reitter, Paul and Chad Wellmon. 2021. Permanent Crisis: The Humanities in a Disenchanted Age. The University of Chicago Press.

Sanders, Andy F. 2016. D.Z. Phillips’ Contemplative Philosophy of Religion: Questions and Responses. London: Routledge.

Sweetman, Brendan. 2014. “D.Z. Phillips on Christian Belief, Immortality, and Resurrection.” Philosophia Christi 16 (1): 57–80.

Thompson, Evan. 2010. Mind in Life: Biology, Phenomenology, and the Sciences of Mind. Harvard University Press.

Van Herck, Walter. 2016. “A Friend of Demea? The Meaning and Importance of Piety.” In D.Z. Phillips’ Contemplative Philosophy Of Religion: Questions and Responses, edited by Andy F. Sanders, 125-138. London: Routledge.

Van Herck, Walter and Paul Cortois. 2004. “Religious Epistemology, Rationality and Trust: An Introduction.” Bijdragen: Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie en Theologie.-Leuven, 1953-2012 60 (4): 373–379

Varela, Francisco J., Eleanor Rosch, and Evan Thompson. 1991. The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Viano, Cristina. 2018. “Byzantine Alchemy, or the Era of Systematization.” In Oxford Handbook of Science and Medicine in the Classical World, edited by John Scarborough and Paul Keyser, 943-964. Oxford University Press.

Whittaker, John H. 2008. “D.Z. Phillips and Reasonable Belief.” In Ethics of Belief: Essays in Tribute to D.Z. Phillips, edited by Eugene Thomas Long and Patrick Horn, 103–129. Dordrecht: Springer.

Wilson, Andrew. 2000. “Drainage and Sanitation.” In Ancient Water Technology (Technology and Change in History 2), edited by Örjan Wikander, 151–179. Leiden: Brill.

Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 2020. The Mythology in Our Language: Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough. HAU Books.


[1] Elaborated further in his later response to Walter van Herck’s objections (2016).

[2] See for instance the letters of Desert Fathers Barsanuphius and John in which they explain to their fellow Christians how they were to pray (Barsanuphius and John. (2007)).

[3] When I speak of the concept of natural law at the time of the Desert Fathers, I use the expression metaphorically to refer to the regularities in nature that alchemists, doctors, architects etc. relied on. But strictly speaking, the concept of natural law came into use in the 17th century. Before then, Aristotelian metaphysics centred on the nature of objects, and that nature set the objects in motion to fulfil their purpose (for a discussion, see Harrison 2020, 215)

[4] See Milbank (2022) for a more nuanced history.

[5] Analytic philosophers were not the only ones working on separating sciences from other areas of human endeavour. For a discussion, see Reitter and Wellmon (2021).



Categories: Articles

Tags: , , , , , , , , ,

1 reply

  1. Kant of all people has a nice reflection on prayer in his Lectures on Ethics! In petitionary prayer we recognize the dependance of creatures on the divine even for their mundane good and it is this consciousness that is the end of that form of prayer. He doesn’t discuss the problem of how this state of mind relates to causal determinism in nature though older thinkers would have held that there was already a pre-established harmony between efficacious prayers and the natural events that fulfill them so that strictly speaking no ‘miracle’ was required.

Leave a Reply

Discover more from Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective

Subscribe now to keep reading and get access to the full archive.

Continue reading